Berlin by Night, by Lesser Ury

Existence Precedes Essence: What Sartre Really Meant

There is no human nature, Jean-Paul Sartre argues, there is only a human condition. Having been ‘thrown’ into the world, we constantly create and recreate ourselves as our lives unfold.

Jack Maden
By Jack Maden  |  August 2023

10-MIN BREAK  

In his 1943 work Being and Nothingness, the existentialist philosopher Jean-Paul Sartre offers the following pithy statement, which he saw as the first principle of existentialism:

Existence precedes essence.

But what does this mean?

Well, Sartre is trying to sloganize a fundamental idea of existentialist philosophy: that we are ‘thrown’ into existence without any kind of fixed essence or substance.

There is no human ‘nature’, Sartre argues, there is only a human condition: we exist as self-conscious first-person perspectives constantly imagining and reimagining who we are as we move through time.

Existentialists Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir
French philosophers Jean-Paul Sartre and Simone de Beauvoir in a Parisian cafe in 1946.

In other words, being conscious of our own existences is the most fundamental thing about what it means to be a human being.

There is no predefined ‘subject’; there is no fixed identity; there is no pre-ordained path or objective. Existence precedes essence, Sartre implores: the very fact of our existence comes first.

It is then up to us, ever-projecting forward into future possibilities, to use our existences to shape our own natures and values, to create whatever ‘essence’ — whatever human being — we choose to become.

As Sartre puts it in his 1946 lecture, Existentialism Is a Humanism:

Man first of all exists, encounters himself, surges up in the world — and defines himself afterwards.

Existence precedes essence: the constraints

While they think existence does indeed precede essence, existentialist philosophers do acknowledge that our self-conscious, first-person existences face a number of constraints.

Namely: we are embodied, replete with appetites and desires, and placed in particular histories and cultural contexts — we are, as the German philosopher Heidegger put it, being-in-the-world, enmeshed in networks of meaning. (See Heidegger’s discussion of authenticity).

Pre-existing identities and meanings will thus be thrust upon us. French philosopher Simone de Beauvoir notably analyzed this in relation to gender roles with her 1949 work, The Second Sex, the second section of which begins with the famous line:

One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman.

(For more here, see Beauvoir on why authentic love involves shedding such predefined, self-limiting roles, as well my reading list of Beauvoir’s best books).

Sartre, too, in his later work, allowed a larger role for social conditioning, writing that man is best understood as

a totally conditioned social being who does not render back completely what his conditioning has given him.

Around the same time, W. E. B. Du Bois, Frantz Fanon and others applied a similar existential analysis to the construction of racial identity, which we discuss in our interview with contemporary philosopher of Black Existentialism, Lewis Gordon.

But what most existentialist thinkers want to argue is that even these inherited qualities — the bodies, families, and societies we are born into — do not have to fix us in place: while we are constrained by them, we simultaneously have the ability to exceed or transcend them, to affirm or deny the cultures we are thrown into, to surpass the identities we are given, and thus to choose our own values and meanings.

As the 20th-century Spanish philosopher José Ortega y Gasset writes, the human being is

a kind of ontological centaur, half immersed in nature, half transcending it.

We are not fixed; we are ever-changing, ever-becoming, ever-redefining: we have the power to create meaning for ourselves through our choices and actions.

Importantly, this doesn’t mean we can do anything we like; rather it means we can interpret ourselves and our situation however we like, and thus shape the person that we are.

As De Beauvoir puts it in her 1947 work, The Ethics of Ambiguity:

To be free is not to have the power to do anything you like; it is to be able to surpass the given towards an open future...

The upshot of existence precedes essence — and the kind of freedom it implies — is well articulated by the contemporary philosopher Kevin Aho in a 2023 essay. Aho writes that

existence is structured by our capacity to give meaning to our situation based on the actions and choices we make as our lives unfold. Insofar as we exist, we are envisioning a certain kind of life, assigning a value to our identity, and making ourselves into the kind of person we are.

We are condemned to be free

The question, then, boils down to this: how should we use our freedom? What interpretations and choices should we make? If we are free to transcend our constraints, to construct our own ‘essences’, to craft the perspectives we want, then what should we do?

Writing a century before Sartre, the Danish philosopher Soren Kierkegaard noted that when we look for answers outside our own subjectivity, we suffer alienation, apathy, nihilism — for, as meaning-giving creatures, it is we ourselves who must offer and affirm them (see our brief explainer of Kierkegaard on the meaning of life here, our article on his observation that while we understand life backwards we must live it forwards here, and our reading list of Kierkegaard’s best books here).

Though we are born into cultures of shared symbols and meanings that impinge on our first-person perspectives, ultimately it is we who are responsible for affirming, rejecting, or creating the values by which we govern our lives.

While perhaps liberating on the one hand, that we bear total responsibility for who we are and what we get from life is a major source of anxiety on the other. There is no divine will, no moral absolute, no natural law upon which we might depend: we are responsible for ourselves.

Sartre goes as far to say that we are thus in fact ‘condemned’ to be free, writing:

Man is condemned to be free. Condemned, because he did not create himself; because, once hurled into the world, he is responsible for everything he does.

Kierkegaard also discusses this thought — that our existential freedom leads to anxiety about the limitless possibilities available to us — in his 1844 work, The Concept of Anxiety:

Anxiety may be compared with dizziness. He whose eye happens to look down the yawning abyss becomes dizzy. But what is the reason for this? It is just as much in his own eye as in the abyss, for suppose he had not looked down. Hence, anxiety is the dizziness of freedom, which emerges when the spirit wants to posit the synthesis and freedom looks down into its own possibility, laying hold of finiteness to support itself.

Every choice we make in life affirms a particular value; anxiety is the dizziness that comes from being conscious of this freedom and responsibility.

If existence precedes essence, if we are responsible for ourselves, then authenticity should be our guide

Given the anguish of responsibility, it is tempting to give in and fall back on identities and meanings already assigned to us — to surrender to the idea that there is a human nature and that I am determined by my given body / circumstances / culture.

Rather than face up to our freedom, we might find it easier or more comfortable to live according to societal norms and the expectations of others.

Existentialists all agree, however, that we are wrong to do this. Suppressing our own freedom is not how we live good lives; playing a part, not being true to ourselves — this will ultimately make us miserable.

While the existentialists present diverse answers to the question of how we should live with radical freedom, the unifying theme of their recommendations is authenticity: to freely do what is valuable not according to external sources or pressures, but according to you.

Inauthenticity — or ‘bad faith’, as Sartre calls it — is when we let our own existential freedom be inhibited through complacency or conformity, when we let other things or people dictate value or define us, when we fix ourselves to static roles or identities rather than recognize ourselves as ever-becoming beings. (For more here, see my explainer on Sartre’s famous discussion of the waiter and bad faith.)

If there were an existential imperative for self-governance, it would be this: never deny your own freedom. (Or, indeed, that of others). Life is endlessly unfolding, and so is your being.

Existential heroes: role models for authenticity

To grant us more insight into what authentic freedom means in practice, existentialist thinkers present us with a number of what we might call ‘existential heroes’ throughout their works.

It might seem strange to pick out existential heroes: surely the point of authenticity is that we must forge our own paths, not copy other people’s.

But existential heroes are not there to be copied; their purpose is to serve as models of how to maintain authenticity in the face of corrupting societies and an inherently meaningless, valueless cosmos (for more on facing up to an apparently meaningless reality, see how Robert Nozick suggests we can live meaningfully in a vast universe).

Existential heroes serve to inspire us to break out of complacency, resist comforting conformity, and carve our own paths.

There is Kierkegaard’s Knight of Faith, someone “willing to be one’s own self”; there is Hedeigger’s Resolute Dasein, someone able to “pull themselves together” from being lost and scattered in “the They”; and perhaps most famously there is Nietzsche’s Übermensch, a being whose continual becoming depends not on external systems but on their own created values (for more here, check out my Übermensch explainer).

And, if these existential heroes don’t do it for us — if, in fact, we harbor suspicions that all our meaning-making projects are ultimately doomed to failure and absurdity — then perhaps it is the absurdist hero of Sisyphus upon whom we might base our approach to authenticity, as suggested by French thinker Albert Camus in his famous 1942 essay, the The Myth of Sisyphus.

For, if ultimate meaning remains forever inaccessible to us, Camus posits, perhaps we can nevertheless establish purpose — even happiness — in the mere act of striving (for more here, see my explainer of Sisyphus, Camus, and his response to absurdity).

Are we as free to shape our lives as the existentialists think?

One major assumption underlying the existentialist view outlined thus far — i.e. that we are free to perpetually create and recreate ourselves as our lives unfold — is that, well, we are in fact free to do so.

Hard determinists suggest free will is an illusion: that though we may feel free, our wills are actually determined by circumstances beyond our control.

In his 1677 work Ethics, the philosopher Baruch Spinoza puts this position succinctly:

There is in the mind no absolute or free will; but the mind is determined in willing this or that by a cause which is determined in its turn by another cause, and this by another, and so on to infinity… People think themselves free because they are conscious of their volitions and desires — but they are ignorant of the causes by which they’re led to wish and desire.

Such a position might seem to be entirely incompatible with the existentialist project, for it suggests we can never transcend the causal chains that constrains us, and thus never really choose anything for ourselves: everything is chosen for us by relentless determinism, regardless of the delusional coping mechanisms we invent to pretend otherwise.

If free will turned out to be an illusion, would that prove fatal to the existentialist project of perpetual self-creation?

Well, not every approach to self-creation necessarily involves free will. Nietzsche, for instance, rejects free will, but also rejects determinism. The whole debate, he suggests, rests on an error: mistaking our descriptions of reality for reality itself.

As he puts it in §21 of his 1886 work Beyond Good and Evil (which features in our reading list of Nietzsche’s best books), in a substantial yet illuminating passage:

Suppose someone sees through the boorish naivete of this famous concept of ‘free will’ and manages to get it out of his mind; I would then ask him to carry his ‘enlightenment’ a step further and to rid his mind of the reversal of this misconceived concept of ‘free will’: I mean the ‘un-free will,’ which is basically an abuse of cause and effect. We should not erroneously objectify ‘cause’ and ‘effect’ like the natural scientists do (and whoever else thinks naturalistically these days -) in accordance with the dominant mechanistic stupidity which would have the cause push and shove until it ‘effects’ something; we should use ‘cause’ and ‘effect’ only as pure concepts, which is to say as conventional fictions for the purpose of description and communication, not explanation. In the ‘in-itself’ there is nothing like ‘causal association,’ ‘necessity,’ or ‘psychological un-freedom.’ There, the ‘effect’ does not follow ‘from the cause,’ there is no rule of ‘law.’ We are the ones who invented causation, succession, for-each-other, relativity, compulsion, numbers, law, freedom, grounds, purpose; and if we project and inscribe this symbol world onto things as an ‘in-itself,’ then this is the way we have always done things, namely mythologically. The ‘un-free will’ is mythology; in real life it is only a matter of strong and weak wills.

Following this critique, Nietzsche develops an account of the human being as both “creature and creator” — that a mediated freedom can arise from the ‘drives’ and ‘impulses’ that make us up.

While the free will debate rages on, Nietzsche’s approach perhaps provides one option for how existentialist thinkers might defend their projects of self-creation from hard determinism.

Learn more about existentialism

Sartre believed the insight captured by his slogan — existence precedes essence — to be of fundamental importance. That we are free to transcend the identities given to us; that there is no human nature, only a human condition; that it is our own subjectivity that must ultimately define meaning and value — these are powerful, if rather audacious, thoughts (indeed, find a defense of human nature in the philosopher Mary Midgley’s reflections on the nature vs. nurture debate).

What do you make of Sartre’s slogan? Do you think the insights of existentialism are true, or that they’re more a coping mechanism for life? Do you agree that existence precedes essence? Or do you think we are born into identities, roles, obligations — even fates — from which we cannot so easily release ourselves?

If you’re interested in learning more about existentialist philosophy, consider checking out my brief introduction to existentialism as both a movement and philosophy. You might also like my reading list of existentialism’s best books.

Finally, if you’re interested in comparing existentialism — including its insights on authenticity, freedom, meaning, and the good life — to 6 other philosophical approaches to life, then consider exploring my new guide, How to Live a Good Life (According to 7 of the World’s Wisest Philosophies), which weighs up the wisdom of 7 rival philosophies for life.

About the Author

Jack Maden

Jack MadenFounder
Philosophy Break

Having received great value from studying philosophy for 15+ years (picking up a master’s degree along the way), I founded Philosophy Break in 2018 as an online social enterprise dedicated to making the subject’s wisdom accessible to all. Learn more about me and the project here.

If you enjoy learning about humanity’s greatest thinkers, you might like my free Sunday email. I break down one mind-opening idea from philosophy, and invite you to share your view.

Subscribe for free here, and join 11,500+ philosophers enjoying a nugget of profundity each week (free forever, no spam, unsubscribe any time).

Philosophy Break
WEEKLY EMAILS

Get one mind-opening philosophical idea distilled to your inbox every Sunday (free)

Philosophy Basics

From the Buddha to Nietzsche: join 11,500+ subscribers enjoying a nugget of profundity from the great philosophers every Sunday:

    ★★★★★ (50+ reviews for Philosophy Break). Unsubscribe any time.

    Philosophy Basics

    Take Another Break

    Each break takes only a few minutes to read, and is crafted to expand your mind and spark your philosophical curiosity.

    Stormy Sea at Night, by Ivan Aivazovsky
    The Sun, Edvard Munch (c. 1911)
    Storm in the Mountains, Albert Bierstadt (c. 1870)
    Heidegger On Authenticity, the They, and Everydayness

    View All Breaks